Walk on countable ordinals: the characteristics

In this post, we shall present a few aspects of the method of walk on ordinals (focusing on countable ordinals), record its characteristics, and verify some of their properties. All definitions and results in this post are due to Todorcevic.

Let Cαα<ω1 be a sequence such that Cα+1={α} for all α<ω1, and for all limit α<ω1: Cα is a cofinal subset of α of order-type ω. Given α<β<ω1, define

    • Tr(α,β)ωω1, by recursively letting for all n<ω:

Tr(α,β)(n):={β,n=0min(CTr(α,β)(n1)α),n>0 & Tr(α,β)(n1)>αα,otherwise

  • ρ2(α,β):=min{n<ωTr(α,β)(n)=α};
  • ρ1ββω, by ρ1β(α):=maxρ0(α,β), where:
  • ρ0(α,β):=otp(CTr(α,β)(j)α)j<ρ2(α,β);
  • L(α,β):={maxijsup(CTr(α,β)(i)α)j<ρ2(α,β)};
  • tr(α,β):=Tr(α,β)ρ2(α,β).

Remark: We consider tr(α,α),ρ0(α,α) and L(α,α) as the empty set.

Notation: Write Ω:={α<ω1cf(α)=ω}. Also, by A=BC, we mean that:

  • A=BC;
  • B, C;
  • (B)(C).

Proposition 1. If δΩ and δ<β<ω1, then max(L(δ,β))<δ.
Proof. If δmax(L(δ,β)), then by definition, there exists i<ρ2(δ,β) such that sup(CTr(δ,β)(i)δ)=δ.  In particular, there exists an ordinal α with  δ<α<β such that sup(Cαδ)=δ. It follows that cf(δ)otp(Cαδ)<otp(Cα)ω, contradicting the fact that δΩ. ◻

Proposition 2. For every α<β<γ<ω1: if α>max(L(β,γ)), then tr(α,γ)=tr(β,γ)tr(α,β).Proof. It suffices to prove that under the same hypotheses, Tr(β,γ)=Tr(α,γ)ρ2(β,γ), and Tr(α,γ)(ρ2(β,γ))=β.
Clearly, Tr(α,γ)(0)=γ=Tr(β,γ)(0). Next, if i<ρ2(β,γ) and Tr(α,γ)(i)=Tr(β,γ)(i), then by β>α>max(L(β,γ))sup(CTr(β,γ)(i)β), we get that min(Ctr(α,γ)(i)α)=min(Ctr(β,γ)(i)α)=min(Ctr(β,γ)(i)β), and hence Tr(α,γ)(i+1)=Tr(β,γ)(i+1). ◻

Proposition 3. For every α<β<γ<ω1: if   min(L(α,β))>max(L(β,γ)), then L(α,γ)=L(β,γ)L(α,β).Proof. By αmin(L(α,β))>max(L(β,γ)), we get from the previous porposition that tr(α,γ)=tr(β,γ)tr(α,β), and hence L(α,γ)=L(β,γ)U, for U:=L(α,β)(max(L(β,γ))+1). Recalling that min(L(α,β))>max(L(β,γ)), we conclude that L(α,γ)=L(β,γ)L(α,β). ◻

Proposition 4. For every α<ω1 and n<ω: the set {ξ<αρ1α(ξ)n} is finite.
Proof. Suppose not. Let α<ω1 be the least for which there exists n<ω and a set Γ[α]ω with ρ1α(γ)n for all γΓ. In particular, otp(Cαγ)n for all γΓ.
Define o:Γn+1 by stipulating that o(γ):=otp(Cαγ). Then there exists Γ[Γ]ω on which o is constant. In particular, min(Cαγ1)=min(Cαγ2) for all γ1,γ2Γ. Put α:=min(Cαmin(Γ)). Then Γ[α]ω, and so by α<α and minimality of the latter, we may find some γΓ such that ρ1α(γ)>n.
By min(Cαγ)=α, we have  tr(γ,α)=αtr(γ,α), and hence ρ1α(γ)=max{otp(Cαγ),ρ1α(γ)}>n. This is a contradiction. ◻

Proposition 5.  For every α<β<ω1, the set {ξ<αρ1α(ξ)ρ1β(ξ)} is finite.
Proof. Suppose not. Let β<ω1 be the least for which there exists α<β and a subset Γα of order-type ω with ρ1α(ξ)ρ1β(ξ) for all ξΓ. Put γ:=sup(Γ), γ:=sup(Cβγ), and  γ+:=min(Cβγ).
By cf(γ)=ωotp(Cβ), we infer that γ<γαγ+<β.
Put n:=otp(Cβγ), and Γ:={ξΓγρ1β(ξ)>n}. By the previous proposition, we know that otp(Γ)=ω. It then follows from γ+<β and minimality of the latter, that there exists ξΓ such that ρ1α(ξ)=ρ1γ+(ξ).
By γξ<γγ+, we know that min(Cβξ)=min(Cβγ) and otp(Cβξ)=otp(Cβγ)=n. That is, min(Cβξ)=γ+, and ρ1γ+(ξ)>otp(Cβξ). So tr(ξ,β)=βtr(ξ,γ+), and hence ρ1β(ξ)=max{otp(Cβξ),ρ1γ+(ξ)}=ρ1γ+(ξ)=ρ1α(ξ). This is a contradiction. ◻

Proposition 6.  For every α<β<ω1, the set {ξ<αρ0(ξ,α)=ρ0(ξ,β)} is closed.
Proof. Let δ be a limit point of this set. Then, by Proposition 1, max(L(δ,β))<δ and max(L(δ,α))<δ. Consequently, we may find ξ in this set such that max(L(δ,α)L(δ,β))<ξ. It then follows from proposition 2 that:

  • tr(ξ,α)=tr(δ,α)tr(ξ,δ);
  • tr(ξ,β)=tr(δ,β)tr(ξ,δ).

Write n:=dom(tr(ξ,δ)). Then tr(δ,α) is equal to tr(ξ,α)(dom(tr(ξ,α))n), and hence ρ0(δ,α) is equal to ρ0(ξ,α)(dom(tr(ξ,α))n). Likewise, ρ0(δ,β) is equal to ρ0(ξ,β)(dom(tr(ξ,β))n). Recalling that ρ0(ξ,α)=ρ0(ξ,β), we conclude that indeed ρ0(δ,α)=ρ0(δ,β). ◻

This entry was posted in Blog, Expository and tagged . Bookmark the permalink.

2 Responses to Walk on countable ordinals: the characteristics

  1. Tanmay Inamdar says:

    Hi Assaf, I found a couple of typos:

    1) In the second last line of the proof of Proposition 4, the theta should be an n.

    2) In the second line of the proof of Proposition 6, the last alpha should be a delta.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *