Polychromatic colorings

These are lectures notes of two talks Dani Livne gave in our Infinite Combinatorics seminar. I did not take notes in real-time, hence, all possible mistakes here are due to myself.

Recall that a function f:AB is said to be θ-to-1 if for every bB, the preimage f1{b} has size θ. It is said to be θ-bounded iff f1{b} has size θ for all bB.

Recall also that κ(λ)θδ stands for the assertion that for every function f:[κ]δθ, there exists some Hκ of order-type λ such that H is monochromatic for f, that is, f[H]δ is constant. Next, we deal with another extreme: κpoly(λ)θboundedδ asserts that for every θ-bounded function f:[κ]2κ, there exists some subset Rκ of type λ such that R is rainbow for f, that is, f[R]δ is injective.

The relation between the above two concepts is as follows.

Proposition (Galvin). κ(λ)θδ entails κpoly(λ)θboundedδ.
Proof. Suppose that f:[κ]δκ is θ-bounded. For every γ<κ, let gγ:θf1{γ} be a surjection. Finally, define h:[κ]δθ by stipulating:h(v¯)=min{i<θgf(v¯)(i)=v¯}. Let Hκ be homogeneous for h of type λ. That is, f[H]δ is constant, with value, say i. We claim that H is rainbow for f. Indeed, if v¯,u¯[H]δ are such that f(v¯)=f(u¯), say it is equal to γ. Then gγ(i)=v¯ and gγ(i)=u¯, which is a contradiction. ◻

So, it follows from Ramsey’s theorem ω(ω)22 that ωpoly(ω)2bounded2 holds. As Sierpinski showed that ω1(ω1)22 fails, the study of ω1poly(ω1)2bounded2 becomes of interest.

Todorcevic proved that ω1poly(ω1)2bounded2 follows from PFA. Here, we shall verify the consistency of the converse.

Theorem (Galvin, private letters to Todorcevic. The proof has appeared in Abraham-Cummings-Smyth, 2007). The Continuum Hypothesis entails a function f:[ω1]2[ω1]2 such that:

  1. f is 2-to-1;
  2. f[A]2 is not 1-to-1 for any uncountable Aω1.

Proof. The proof is a variation of an argument of Erdos-Hajnal-Milner. In particular, the consequence of CH that we shall utilize, is the existence of a sequence Aδδ<ω1 of infinite bounded subsets of ω1 with the property that for every unbounded subset A of ω1, there exists some δ<ω1 such that AδA (the so-called stick principle).

To start with, pick an arbitrary g:[ω]2[ω]2 which is 2-to-1. Then let f[ω]2 coincide with g. Next, fix an infinite ordinal β<ω1, and let us define f(β×{β}). Let {Xnβn<ω} be some (not necessarily injective) enumeration of {Aδδ<β,Aδβ}{β}. Since Xnβ is infinite for all n<ω, it is easy to recursively define a function φβ:ω[β]3 with the properties:

  1. φβ(n)φβ(m)= for all n<m<ω;
  2. φβ(n)Xnβ for all n<ω.

Define φβ:ω[β]2 by letting φβ(n):=φβ(n){maxφβ(n)} for all n<ω. Since βφβ[ω] is infinite, it is now easy to pick a function ψβ:ω[β]2 such that:

  1. ψβ(n)ψβ(m)= for all n<m<ω;
  2. ψβ[ω]=βφβ[ω].

Write Pβ:=φβ[ω]ψβ[ω]. Then Pβ is a partition of β into cells of size 2. Thus, given α<β, we find the unique cell cPβ such that αc, and let f(α,β):=(min(c),β). This completes the definition of f. Evidently, f is indeed 2-to-1.

Finally, suppose that A is an uncountable subset of ω1. Fix δ<ω1 such that AδA. Fix a large enough βA such that β>δ and Aδβ. Let n<ω be such that Aδ=Xnβ. Let α<γ<β be such that φβ(n)={α,γ}. Then {α,γ,β}A and f(α,β)=(α,β)=f(γ,β). So f[A]2 is not injective. ◻

Our next goal is to establish the failure of κpoly(ω)2boundedω for every infinite cardinal κ. We commence with a couple of lemmas.

Lemma 1. There exist injections f:[ω]ω[ω]ω,g:[ω]ω[ω]ω such that:

  1. f(x),g(x) are a proper subset of x, for all x[ω]ω;
  2. rng(f)rng(g)=.

Proof. Let be some well-ordering of [ω]ω in order-type 20. Define f(x),g(x) by recursion. Given x[ω]ω such that f(y),g(y) are defined for all yx, let:

  • f(x):=min({z[x]ωzx}{f(y),g(y)yx});
  • g(x):=min({z[x]ωzx}({f(y),g(y)yx}{f(x)})).

Note that the definition is good since |[x]ω|>|{y[ω]ωyx}|+1 for all x[ω]ω. ◻

Lemma 2. For every infinite cardinal κ, there exist injections f:[κ]ω[κ]ω,g:[κ]ω[κ]ω such that:

  1. f(x),g(x) are a proper subset of x, for all x[κ]ω;
  2. rng(f)rng(g)=.

Proof. Let {aαα<λ} be some maximal almost-disjoint (MAD) family in [κ]ω. That is:

  • aα[κ]ω for all α<λ;
  • aαaβ is finite for all α<β<λ;
  • for every x[κ]ω, there exists some α<λ such that xaα is infinite.

Of course, the existence of such a family is a consequence of Zorn’s lemma (i.e., of the axiom of choice). Recalling the previous lemma, we then fix for every α<λ, injections fα:[aα]ω[aα]ω,gα:[aα]ω[aα]ω such that:

  1. fα(x),gα(x) are a proper subset of x, for all x[aα]ω;
  2. rng(fα)rng(gα)=.

Then, for all x[κ]ω, we let αx be the least α<λ such that xaα is infinite, and put

  • f(x):=fαx(xaαx)(xaαx);
  • g(x):=gαx(xaαx)(xaαx).

We now verify that f,g are injections, and that rng(f),rng(g) are disjoint. For this fix x,y[κ]ω, h{f,g}, and suppose that f(x)=h(y).

If αx=αy=α, then by f(x)=h(y), we get in particular that fα(xaα)=hα(yaα), and hence h=f (since gα,fα have disjoint ranges), which in turn implies that xaα=yaα (since fα is injective). Recalling that f(x)=f(y) entails also that xaα=yaα, we conclude that x=y.

If αx<αy, then aαxaαy is finite, and in particular fαx(xaαx)hαy(yaαy) is finite. So, from f(x)=h(y), we infer the existence of a finite set F, such that fαx(xaαx)F(yaαy). In particular, aαxy is infinite, contradicting the minimality of αy. So this case is void. ◻

Theorem (Palumbo-Tserunyan, 2012). κpoly(ω)2boundedω fails for every infinite cardinal κ.
Proof. Let f,g be as in Lemma 2. Define c:[κ]ω[κ]ω×2 as follows. Given x[κ]ω. If there exists y[κ]ω such that f(y)=x, then y is unique, and we let c(x):=(y,0). If there exists y[κ]ω such that g(y)=x, then y is again unique, and we let c(x):=(y,0). If x(rng(f)rng(g)), then let c(x):=(x,1). Since f,g are injectives, we get that c is 2-bounded (actually, we could have been slightly more careful and insure that c is strictly 2-to-1). Finally, to see that c admits no infinite rainbow set, fix an arbitrary x[κ]ω. Then, we have:

  • {f(x),g(x)}[x]ω;
  • c(f(x))=(x,0)=c(g(x)).

So, c[x]ω is not 1-to-1. ◻

This entry was posted in Blog, Expository and tagged , . Bookmark the permalink.

2 Responses to Polychromatic colorings

  1. Literature says:

    The CH-result is due to Galvin (as well as its proof). It is mentioned in Todorcevic’s paper whose link you provide (page 43 lines 11-12). It is curious that you don’t mention the remark on page 43, line 13 of the same paper. Galvin’s original notation for this partition symbol is in my opinion much better as it points out the duality to the ordinary partition symbol.

    • saf says:

      Sorry about that. Indeed, in Todorcevic’s paper as well as in the Abraham-Cummings-Smyth paper, the CH result is attributed to Galvin.

      Thanks for the correction!

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *