Here is an elementary proof of (the finitary version of) the
Lemma. Suppose that
Then there exists a subcollection
Proof. Without loss of generality
The proof is by induction.
Induction base: The case
Induction step: Suppose that
- If there exists
such that has size , then by the hypothesis, we may find of size , and an ordinal such that for all .
Then, , and are as needed. - If
for all , then utilizing the regularity of , we can recursively construct a mapping such that for all .
Then, and are as desired.
This completes the proof.
Bonus question: what’s the relation between the assertion we just proved by induction and the stunning photo above?
The Nile.
Indeed, we have for all . I wonder why don’t they call it the -system lemma!
When you are looking at it from the Greek side of the globe, it’s really a .
According to the convention of drawing ordinals from bottom to up, the equation “ for all distinct ” corresponds to .
But maybe this notation was conceived by the same people who decided that forcing should go up?
Halfway backwards sort of approach…
This seems to be the proof in Shelah’s proper forcing book. Congratulations on the Bar-Ilan position, by the way.
Thanks, Andres.
I see! Well, the first proof I’ve ever seen to this lemma was given in Gitik’s course in Tel-Aviv, following Hrbacek and Jech; their proof involves iterative applications of the pressing-down lemma. The other proof I know is the elementary submodel proof, which morally is the same as pressing-down. Thus, the above proof-by-induction came to me as a surprise!
At some point, I thought it may be possible to find another proof that builds on the fact that is separable, yielding a color-by-type map in a way that an homogeneous set corresponds to a delta-system. However, a counting argument shows that this is impossible.
Isn’t this the proof used in Kunen’s “set theory” book? This I think predates Shelah’s book as well.
Thank you, Henno! -systems, and hence not of this form. However, you are right – Exercise 1 from Chapter II suggests the above proof.
The proof in Kunen’s book is for the general case of
Pingback: An L-space from a syndetic coloring and a universal binary sequence | Assaf Rinot
It is a silly question but how do you construct the function ?
You can define by recursion on , stipulating that .
Since is regular and for all , we have for all , and hence the function is well-defined.
Finally, let be an arbitrary element of for all .
In the second part of the induction step: can't we just define a regressive function where ? , we get to the first part of the induction step?
If
And then, by fodor's Lemma and the regularity of
The domain of is the (rather sparse) set , so, while you can still think of as being regressive, the (generalized) Fodor lemma fails in this setup.
Actually, there is an easier proof (of the Induction step): Either we have a disjoint system of size , or take any maximal disjoint system and some point in its union will belong to many (other) members of (that’s where the regularity of is needed).
Hi Assaf,
Do you know if there is any Ramsey-type theorem that has as consequence the delta system lemma?
Thanks.
Hi Carlos,
Indeed. Given , for each , let denote the increasing enumeration of the elements of . Let us also fix some well-ordering of . Now define a coloring by letting for all from . Let us observe that any that is -homogeneous will form a -system. Indeed, if is constant over with value, say, , and denotes its -least element, consider the set . in that is distinct from , since , it is the case that . Therefore, . In addition, for all from , , so, in fact, .
Now, given any set