In this post, we shall provide a proof to a famous theorem of Murray Bell stating that holds iff .
We commence with defining the cardinal invariant . For sets and , we write iff . We say that is a pseudointersection of a family , if for all . Then, the cardinal stands for the smallest size of a family of subsets of such that any finite subcollection of admits an infinite pseudointersection, while itself does not.
(To see that is well-defined, let be any uniform ultrafilter on . Also, note that a standard diagonlization argument entails that .)
Lemma. If is a countable set, , and is a sequence of functions, then there exists a function such that for all :
Proof. Suppose that is as above. Without loss of generality, and for all and . Fix a bijection . For each and , let
It is trivial to verify that is infinite for every finite and finite . In particular, every finite subset of admits a pseudointersection. By , we then pick a pseudointersection P of . For all , we have , and hence we may let:
Finally, fix , and let us verify that is finite. Fix . Let be such that , and . Since and is increasing, we also get that . So . Thus, we have shown that for every , there exists some with . Since is finite, it must be the case that is finite.
Corollary. Suppose that , and is a collection of subsets of with the property that for every and , the set is infinite.
Then there exists such that is finite for all .
Proof. Since , let us fix for every , an infinite pseudointersection of . For every , this induces a function as follows:
By the preceding lemma, we then get a function such that is finite for all . By pointwise increasing the function , we may moreover assume that for all . Finally, define by letting and, recursively, for all positive .
To see that works, fix . Since is finite, let us pick a large enough such that whenever has . In particular, whenever . Consequently, whenever .
Our next perspective is partial orders. For a poset , and a subset , we write:
Recall that is said to be cofinal in in case that .
Definition. asserts that for every partial order , and every sequence of cofinal subsets of , there exists a subset that satisfies the following two:
- for all ;
- for all .
Observation. holds.
Proof. Given a poset , and a sequence of cofinal subsets of , let us construct an order-preserving injection by recursion on . Let be an arbitrary element of , and let be some element of such that (by utilizing the fact that is cofinal in ). Finally, put .
As is isomorphic to , we see that item (1) above is satisfied. As and , we get in particular that item (2) above is satisfied.
Next, let us study for .
Definition. We say that a poset is -centered if there exists s.t. :
- ;
- for all , is centered, that is, for any finite subset .
Observation. (the class of -centered posets) fails.
Proof. By definition of , it is easy to pick a family such that:
- for any finite subcollection , we have ;
- does not admit an infinite pseudointersection;
- .
Next, consider the poset , where , and if the following three hold:
- ;
- ;
- .
For any finite subset of , denote . Clearly, witnesses that is -centered. Next, for all and define
For any , and , we have , and hence is cofinal. Also, for any and , since is a finite subset of , we have , and hence we may pick some , and infer that . This shows that is cofinal.
Finally, assume towards a contradiction that (the class of -centered posets) does not fail. Then, by , we find a set such that:
- for all ;
- for all ;
- for all .
Let . By clause (3) above, we see that is infinite. Thus, to meet a contradiction, it suffices to show that for all , we have . Fix . By clause (2) above, let us pick such that and . We claim that is contained in the finite set . To see this, pick . By definition of then, there exists some such that . By clause (3) above, let us pick .
By , and , we have .
By , and , we have .
Altogether, either or .
Lemma. For every infinite cardinal , the following are equivalent:
- (the class of -centered posets);
- (the class of -centered posets of size ).
Proof. Suppose that (the class of -centered posets of size ) holds and that is a sequence of cofinal subset of some -centered poset . Let witness that is -centered. Let be an elementary submodel of for a large enough regular cardinal such that and and for all and . Let and . It is easy to see that witnesses that is a -centered poset. For all , put . By elementarity, is cofinal in . As , we then infer the existence of a subset such that
- for all ;
- for all .
In particular, for all , and we are done.
We now arrive to the main result of this post.
Theorem (Bell, 1981). (the class of -centered posets) holds iff .
Proof. By all of the above, it suffices to show that if , then (the class of -centered posets of size ) holds. Thus, let be some -centered poset of size , as witnessed by . Without loss of generality, the set is infinite for all . This will entail that the sets defined below will either be empty or infinite.
Let be a sequence of cofinal subsets of . For any , let
A moment reflection makes it clear that for every , there exists some with . Thus, by , we may assume that
Fix .
- Let be an arbitrary element of .
- Next, if and is defined, then for all , we let be an element of . Whenever possible, we require in addition that be an element of .
For every , let
Next, notice that for every , there exists some such that . As the latter is centered, we then get that for every and , there exists some such that . Since is a finite collection of cofinal sets, it is easy to find . Let be such that , then . So is infinite.
It follows that may invoke the corollary established earlier in this post, and get a function together with such that whenever and . Write , and then put
Given , let us verify that by pointing out that . Indeed, we have and hence has been defined according to the “whenever possible” case.
The same argument shows that if , then is a linearly-ordered set. So for every , if we take , then and . So for all .
Finally, given , pick . Then for some , and hence , as well as . Recalling that , we conclude that , as required.
Pingback: Jones’ theorem on the cardinal invariant p | Assaf Rinot
Pingback: The S-space problem, and the cardinal invariant p | Assaf Rinot