An S-space from a Cohen real

Recall that an S-space is a regular hereditarily separable topological space which is not hereditarily Lindelöf. In this post, we shall establish the consistency of the existence of such a space.

Theorem (Roitman, 1979). Let C=(<ωω,) be the notion of forcing for adding a Cohen real. Then, in the generic extension by forcing with C, there exists an S-space.

The proof we give here is not Roitman’s original argument; I am not sure where did I occur into the version that will be given here.

We commence with a lemma. Its statement requires a piece of notation, as follows. For a set of ordinals a of finite size n, we let {a(0),a(1),,a(n1)} denote the -increasing enumeration of the elements of a.

Lemma. In the generic extension by forcing with C, there exists a coloring f:[ω1]2ω such that for every finite function g:n×nω, and an uncountable A[ω1]n whose elements are pairwise disjoint, there exists some a,bA such that max(a)<min(b) and f(a(i),b(j))=g(i,j) for all i,j<n.

Proof. Work in V. Let {Aαα<ω1} be the injective enumeration of some almost-disjoint family in [ω]ω. For all α<ω, let dα:αω be arbitrary. For all infinite α<ω1, let dα:αAα be some bijection. Next, let G be C-generic over V, and work in V[G]. Put c:=G. Then, define f:[ω1]2ω by letting for all α<β<ω1:f(α,β):=c(dβ(α)).

Next, suppose that n,g and A are as in the statement of the lemma. As g is finite, g belongs to V. As C is countable, A contains an uncountable subcollection that lies in V. Note also that f has a simple (“canonical”) C-name, hence, we shall prove via a density argument.
Fix an aribtrary C-condition, say, p:mω, together with ground model n,g and A. Fix an infinite ordinal δ<ω1 such that sup{min(a)aδ}=δ (e.g., if δ=Mω1 for a countable elementary submodel M(H(ω2),,) with AM). Pick bA such that min(b)>δ. Pick a large enough k<ω such that Ab(i)Ab(j)k for all i<j<n. Put γ:=max{max(db(i)1[k+m])i<n}+1.So, in simple words, γ is a large enough ordinal below δ that satisfies:

  • the elements of {db(i)[δγ]i<n} are pairwise disjoint;
  • fb(i)(α)>k whenever i<n and γα<δ.

By the choice of δ, we can now pick aA such that γ<min(a)max(a)<δ. Then, the map (α,β)dβ(α) is injective over a×b, and its image is disjoint from dom(p). Consequently, it is possible to extend p to a condition q so that q(db(j)(a(i))=g(i,j) for all i,j<n.Evidently, any such q forces that f(a(i),b(j))=g(i,j) for all i,j<n.◻

Proof of main theorem. Fix a coloring f:[ω1]2ω as in the lemma. For every β<ω1, put uβ:={α<βc(α,β)=0}{β}. We say that (I,J) is good pair if I,J[ω1]<ω and IJ=. DenoteU(I,J):={uγγI}{uγγJ}.

We then define B:={U(I,J)(I,J) good pair} as a basis to a topology τ on ω1. Note that X:=ω1,τ is Hausdorff, since α<β<ω1 implies that βuβ and αω1uβ. Also X is zero-dimensional (given the convention that γuγ=ω1), and hence regular.
Note that since uββ+1 for all β<ω1, the cover {uββ<ω1} witnesses that X is not Lindelöf.
Thus, towards a contradiction, suppose that X contains a non-separable subspace Y. Then, one can recursively construct an increasing function ψ:ω1Y so that ψ(β)ψ[β] for all β<ω1. Put Z:=ψ[ω1], and write vβ:=uβ(Zβ) for all βZ. Then vβ is an open neighbourhood around β, and we have αvβ for all αZβ.Fix βZ. As vβ is an open neighbourhood around β, and by definition of τ, we may fix a good pair (Iβ,Jβ) such that β{uγγIβ}{uγγJβ}vβ.As vβuβ, we may also assume that min(Iβ)=β. Next, by passing to an uncountable subcollection ZZ, we may assume the existence of  Aω, and ϵ<ω1 such that:

  1. Zϵ=;
  2. {IββZ} consists of mutually disjoint sets;
  3. {JβϵβZ} consists of mutually disjoint sets;
  4. {JβϵβZ} consists of a single element;
  5. {|Iβ|,|Jβϵ|βZ} consists of a single element, say n,m;
  6. Denote aβ:=Iβ(Jβϵ). Then α<min(aβ) for all α<β in Z;
  7. For all βZ and j<n+m: aβ(j)Iβ iff jA.

Note that items (3),(4) simply say that {JββZ} is a Δ-system, and item (7) asserts that Iβ embeds in aβ in a certain fixed pattern for all βZ.

Put A:={aββZ}, and define g:(n+m)×(n+m)2 by stipulating that g(i,j)=0 iff jA. By the choice of f, we may now pick α<β in Z such that  f(aα(i),aβ(j))=g(i,j) for all i,j<n+m.In particular, for all j<n+m: f(α,aβ(j))=0 iff jA.So, f(α,γ)=0 for all γIβ, and f(α,γ)=1 for all γJβϵ.
Recalling that αvβ{uγγIβ}{uγγJβ}, and the definition of uγ, we get that αuγ for some γJβ. As f(α,γ)=1 for all γJβϵ, we get that γJβϵ. So αuγγ+1ϵ, contradicting the fact that αZ and item (1). ◻

This entry was posted in Blog, Expository and tagged , . Bookmark the permalink.

6 Responses to An S-space from a Cohen real

  1. Pingback: The S-space problem, and the cardinal invariant p | Assaf Rinot

  2. Pingback: The S-space problem, and the cardinal invariant b | Assaf Rinot

  3. Literature says:

    In Chaper 2 (top of page 26) of Todorcevic’s book ‘Partition problems in topology’ one finds a compact S-space from a Cohen real.

  4. Pingback: Syndetic colorings with applications to S and L | Assaf Rinot

  5. Pingback: The S-space problem, and the cardinal invariant mathfrakp | Assaf Rinot

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *