In a previous post, we defined Shelah’s approachability ideal . We remind the reader that a subset is in iff there exists a collection such that for club many , the union contains all the initial segments of some small cofinal subset, , of .
The notion “small” above stands for the assertion that .
It is an interesting fact that in the proofs given in the previous post, the small witnessing sets were always of smallest possible size, i.e., . This raises the question of whether one can get the witnessing sets to have higher order-type. In this post, we shall provide an alternative proof to the fact that for every regular cardinal , in which the witnessing sets would have as large order-type (below ) as we like. As a bonus, the witnessing sets would also have the feature of club guessing.
Theorem (Shelah). For every regular uncountable cardinal , every non-zero limit ordinal , and every stationary set , there exists a sequence such that for every club , there exists an such that:
Proof. For every ordinal , fix an injection . Denote . Then for every , is an increasing and continuous chain in that converges to . Next, for all , we define a club in as follows:
For a set and , we define the set as the set of all for which all of the following holds:
Subclaim 1. There exists an , for which is nonempty whenever is a club in .
Proof. Suppose not. Then for every , we may pick a club for which . Put . Then is a club in , so let us pick some such that .
As , the set is co-bounded in .
Also, continuity entails that the set is a club in . Again, by continuity, we may pick such that is divisible by . Then, by , we get that . So , contradicting the choice of .
Let be given by the previous claim.
Subclaim 2. There exists a club such that for every club , the set is nonempty.
Proof. Suppose not. Then there exists a decreasing and continuous sequence of clubs such that , and for every , the set is empty.
Put , and pick . Then for all , and hence must be a strictly-decreasing sequence of subsets of , contradicting the fact that .
Let be given by the previous claim.
Subclaim 3. There exists an ordinal which is divisible by such that for every club , the set is nonempty.
Proof. Otherwise, for every ordinal which is divisible by , there exists a club for which is empty. Put . By the choice of , then, we may pick such that . Put . Then by , is divisible by , contradicting the fact .
Let be given by the previous claim.
As is divisible by , let us pick a cofinal subset of order-type . Then, define for all :
To see that works. Suppose that we are given a club .
Pick such that and . Then:
- ;
- ;
- ;
- , and hence for all , we have , and ;
- , and .
This completes the proof.
Corollary. For every uncountable cardinal and every ordinal , there exists a sequence satisfying the following.
For every club , every large enough regular cardinal , and any , there exists an elementary submodel such that:
- has size , and ;
- is an ordinal, and ;
- is a club in of type ;
- for all .
Proof. If is a regular cardinal, then we take the sequence provided by the previous theorem, and let denote the closure of . To see that works, suppose that we are given a club . Consider the club of all ordinals of the form for some elementary submodel of size that contains and . By the choice of , we can find some such that is cofinal subset of , of type , , and for all . In particular, , and so we can find a model with and such that for all . As and is closed, we also get that . As for all , we get also that for all .
If is singular, we let . Then, by statement (2) of our previous post, there exists a sequence , and a matrix of bounded subsets of , such that for every club , there exists such that is a club in of type , and for every , there exists and such that . To see that works, suppose that we are given a club . Consider the club of all ordinals of the form for some elementary submodel of size containing and . By the choice of , we can find some such that is a club in , of type , , and any proper initial segment of is an element of . In particular, , and we may fix a model with such that . As , our proof is complete.
We conclude with a couple of a questions concerning possible strengthenings of the above opening theorem:
- What happens if we require that be closed for all ? Does this stronger statement follow from ZFC?
- What happens if we take , and arbitrarily large countable limit ordinal? Does this version follow from ZFC?
(note that here we cannot expect the statement to hold true for any stationary subset )
We mention that a negative answer to (2) entails a negative answer to Question 4 from this paper of Foreman and Todorcevic.