Kurepa trees and ineffable cardinals

Recall that T is said to be a κ-Kurepa tree if T is a tree of height κ, whose levels Tα has size |α| for co-boundedly many α<κ, and such that the set of branches of T has size >κ.

Recall also that an uncountable cardinal κ is said to be ineffable if for every sequence Aαα<κα<κP(α), there exists some Aκ for which the set {α<κAα=Aα} is stationary. Note that every measurable cardinal is ineffable, and that every ineffable cardinal is weakly compact.

Let us point out that these concepts are mutually contradictory.

Proposition (Jensen-Kunen). If κ is an ineffable cardinal, then there is no κ-Kurepa tree.
Proof. Suppose that κ,T is a Kurepa tree, and let F denote the set of its branches. Then |F|>κ, while C:={α<κβ<αTβ=α & |{bαbF}||α|} is a club in κ.

For all αC, we let {bαii<α} be some enumeration of {bαbF}, and then put Xα:=i<α({i}×bαi). Next, Fix a bijection π:κ×κκ, and define Aα:={π[Xα]α,αC,otherwise.

Now, as κ is ineffable, we may find some set Aκ such that the following set is stationary: S={α<κAα=Aα}.

For all i<κ, denote bi:={β<κ(i,β)π1[A]}. As |F|>κ, let us fix some bF{bii<κ}. If follows that we may define a function f:κκ, by letting f(i):=min{α<κbiαbα}.

Since S is stationary, we may fix an αSC such that π[α×α]=α and f[α]α. Let i<α be such that bαi=bα. By the choice of α and since π is a bijection, we get that π1[A](α×α)=π1[Aα]=π1[Aα]=π1[π[Xα]π[α×α]]=Xα.In particular, biα={β<κ(i,β)Xα}={β<κ(i,β)j<α({j}×bαj)}=bαi.Altogether, we got that biα=bα, contradicting the fact that f(i)<α. ◻

This entry was posted in Blog, Expository and tagged . Bookmark the permalink.

9 Responses to Kurepa trees and ineffable cardinals

  1. Assaf, what you call a kappa-Kurepa tree is what I know as a *slim* kappa-Kurepa tree. The forcing to create a slim kappa-Kurepa tree is <kappa-closed, but as you point out, definitely destroys the measurability of kappa. This shows that in Laver's indestructibilty theorem, where a supercompact cardinal kappa is made indestructible by all <kappa-directed closed forcing, one cannot improve it to indestructibility by all <kappa-closed forcing.

    • saf says:

      Thanks for this info, Joel! I wonder what is the more general definition of a kappa-Kurepa tree?

      • The more general definition that I have seen is just a kappa tree (meaning all levels have size less than kappa) with at least kappa+ many branches. This is trivial when kappa is a strong limit, for example, since the full binary tree has the property, and this may be the reason you dont’ consider it. The slimness property I know is essentially the extra property you mention, that the alpha-th level should have size alpha, when alpha is infinite (slight difference from what you say: except for boundedly many alpha).

  2. Furthermore, Thomas Johnstone, Vika Gitman and I proved that one may make any strongly unfoldable cardinal indestructible by the forcing to add a slim kappa-Kurepa tree. (This was generalized in later work: see http://jdh.hamkins.org/indestructiblestrongunfoldability/.) So one can have a strongly unfoldable cardinal with a slim kappa-Kurepa tree, and this provides a bound on improvements to the theorem you mention.

    • saf says:

      That’s very interesting!
      Do you perhaps know of an upper bound for the non-existence of an alephomega+1-Kurepa tree? Dima Sinapova and myself realized this week that a supercompact cardinal and an almost huge cardinal above it, suffices. (This follows from Foreman’s theorem 4.11 in here.)

  3. Mohammad says:

    I assume you mean the alephomega and not alephomega+1.

    • saf says:

      Thanks, Mohammad. I did mean alephomega+1, but later indeed realized that the classic Silver argument will do the job.

  4. Mohammad says:

    Yes, that was why I asked the questio, as the ordinary Levy collapse works foe successor cardinals.

Comments are closed.