Recall that is said to be a -Kurepa tree if is a tree of height , whose levels has size for co-boundedly many , and such that the set of branches of has size .
Recall also that an uncountable cardinal is said to be ineffable if for every sequence , there exists some for which the set is stationary. Note that every measurable cardinal is ineffable, and that every ineffable cardinal is weakly compact.
Let us point out that these concepts are mutually contradictory.
Proposition (Jensen-Kunen). If is an ineffable cardinal, then there is no -Kurepa tree.
Proof. Suppose that is a Kurepa tree, and let denote the set of its branches. Then , while is a club in .
For all , we let be some enumeration of , and then put . Next, Fix a bijection , and define
Now, as is ineffable, we may find some set such that the following set is stationary:
For all , denote As , let us fix some . If follows that we may define a function , by letting
Since is stationary, we may fix an such that and . Let be such that . By the choice of and since is a bijection, we get that In particular, Altogether, we got that , contradicting the fact that . 
Assaf, what you call a -Kurepa tree is what I know as a *slim* -Kurepa tree. The forcing to create a slim -Kurepa tree is -closed, but as you point out, definitely destroys the measurability of . This shows that in Laver's indestructibilty theorem, where a supercompact cardinal is made indestructible by all -directed closed forcing, one cannot improve it to indestructibility by all -closed forcing.
Thanks for this info, Joel! I wonder what is the more general definition of a -Kurepa tree?
The more general definition that I have seen is just a tree (meaning all levels have size less than ) with at least many branches. This is trivial when is a strong limit, for example, since the full binary tree has the property, and this may be the reason you dont’ consider it. The slimness property I know is essentially the extra property you mention, that the -th level should have size , when is infinite (slight difference from what you say: except for boundedly many ).
Indeed, any definition that omits a slimness condition is likely to trivialize the matter.
Furthermore, Thomas Johnstone, Vika Gitman and I proved that one may make any strongly unfoldable cardinal indestructible by the forcing to add a slim -Kurepa tree. (This was generalized in later work: see http://jdh.hamkins.org/indestructiblestrongunfoldability/.) So one can have a strongly unfoldable cardinal with a slim -Kurepa tree, and this provides a bound on improvements to the theorem you mention.
That’s very interesting! -Kurepa tree? Dima Sinapova and myself realized this week that a supercompact cardinal and an almost huge cardinal above it, suffices. (This follows from Foreman’s theorem 4.11 in here.)
Do you perhaps know of an upper bound for the non-existence of an
I assume you mean the and not .
Thanks, Mohammad. I did mean , but later indeed realized that the classic Silver argument will do the job.
Yes, that was why I asked the questio, as the ordinary Levy collapse works foe successor cardinals.