Continuing the previous post, let us now prove the following.
Theorem (Erdos-Dushnik-Miller, 1941). For every singular cardinal λ, we have:
Proof. Suppose that is a singular cardinal, and is a given coloring. For any ordinal , denote .
Subclaim. At least one of the following holds:
- there exists an infinite subset for which ;
- there exists a subset of size , such that for all .
Proof. Suppose that (2) fails. Recursively define a seuqence as follows:
– , and is a witness to the fact that is non-empty;
– , and is an element of the non-empty set .
Then implies that . In particular, . So witnesses clause (1). End of proof of subclaim.
Next, let us suppose that for any infinite , and work towards showing that for some subset of size . By our hypothesis, we may fix a subset as in clause (2) of the preceding subclaim. Let be a strictly increasing sequence of regular cardinals converging to , with . Let be some partition of a subset of into pairwise-disjoint sets such that for all . For simplicity, we shall further require that for all .
Denote , and fix .
– Since is regular, we infer from the previous post, the existence of a subset of size such that .
– Since , we get that and since , we infer the existence of some for which
Recursively define a function so that for all , we would have:
Then, for all , let , and notice that the choice of insures that for all . So in particular, is a subset of size .
Finally, to see that , fix in . Let be such that for all . There are two cases to consider:
case 1: . Here, . So, by the choice of , we conclude that .
case 2: . Since , we know that is disjoint from . In particular, is not an element of , meaning that .
To see that the preceding theorem is somewhat optimal, we point out the following.
Proposition (folklore). fails for every uncountable cardinal of countable cofinality.
Proof. Suppose that . Let denote an increasing sequence of ordinals converging to . Define by letting . Define by letting iff .
Evidently, for every that satisfies , we have that is order-preserving. In particular, for any such . On the other front, as for all , we get that for every subset of order-type . Altogether, witnesses the failure of . .
In an upcoming post, we shall provide a proof for Shelah’s recent extension of the Edros-Dushnik-Miller theorem that handles singular cardinals of uncountable cofinality.

I think there’s a problem with the second-last line, where it says c”[A]^2 is infinite. It looks like you meant neq {0}.
That’s right, Ari. What I wanted to say is that is infinite whenever , and hence for every such .
Thanks!
Pingback: Dushnik-Miller for singular cardinals (part 2) | Assaf Rinot