Nik Weaver asked for a direct proof of the fact that Todorcevic’s axiom implies the failure of CH fails. Here goes.
Notation. For a set , we write for the set of unordered pairs .
Definition (Todorcevic’s axiom). If is a separable metric space, and , with open in , then at least one of the following hold:
- there exists an uncountable subset such that ;
- there is a partition such that for all .
Lemma. If , then , i.e., there exists a sequence such that:
- is an increasing function for all ;
- is finite, whenever ;
- for every , there exists some such that is infinite, whenever .
Proof. Since , we can list , as . We then construct by recursion on . Suppose that has already been constructed. Let be some enumeration of . Define by letting for all .
Theorem (Todorcevic). Todorcevic’s axiom implies that .
Proof. Assume TA. Towards a contradiction, suppose that satisfies the above items (1)–(3). Consider as a subspace of the Baire space . Let , where . It is easy to see that is open. Now, let us examine each of the alternatives:
Alternative 2. There is a partition such that for all :
In particular, we may fix an uncountable subset with . Then, for every such that , we have that is empty. Write . Notice that if is finite for all , then we get a contradiction to item (3), hence, we may fix some such that . Pick a large enough such that . Then cannot be an integer. This is a contradiction.
Alternative 1. There exists an uncountable subset with :
In particular, for every such that , we have that is nonempty. Write . Then, for all in , we have , where
Thus, to meet the desired contradiction, it suffices to establish the following.
Subclaim. There exists in such that .
Proof. Since is countable, let us fix a large enough such that for every : if there exists with , then there exists such below .
Write . As , let us fix some such that is uncountable. By item (3) above, we get that the set is nonempty (in fact, infinite), so consider its minimal element, .
For , denote . By minimality of , the set is finite, so we can easily find some such that Since is nonempty, let us fix some below such that . Put , and then pick such that . Of course, . We claim that . This is best seen by dividing into three cases:
- if , then ;
- if , then (recall that the elements of are increasing functions!);
- if , then and , as well as and . Altogether, . End of subclaim
This complete the proof.
Ari B. pointed out (see his comment bel0w) that the proof shows that the axiom SOCA already implies that , where SOCA is the outcome of weakening the second alternative of TA to “there exists an uncountable subset such that ”.

There’s a problem with your statement of Todorcevic’s Axiom. What you’ve stated here is actually the Semi-Open Colouring Axiom.
So it seems that you’ve shown the stronger result that SOCA implies and therefore contradicts CH.
Incidentally, Kunen’s new textbook shows that SOCA implies that there are no weakly Luzin sets in when and therefore contradicts CH.
Thanks. I fixed this, and added your remark about SOCA.
Thanks. But now your paragraphs “Alternative 1” and “…2” in the proof don’t match the alternatives in the statement.
Thanks. Perfected:)
– We might simplify your proof if we note that since are increasing, is the set of couples that are not “totally” increasing (has at least one contra-example).
– Now since in alternative 2 we get such pairs of functions, there must be some that is the witness for decreasinesses-pairs. Looking only at this coordinate, since a decreasing serie of can only be finite, we get a contradication to the fact that we have witnesses.
But it sounds like you are invoking a pigenhole principle for pairs at the level of — a no-go when it comes to successor cardinals.
Hi Assaf,
Isn’t Todorcevic OCA states that either there is uncoutable 0 homogeneous set or a countable decomposition of X into 1-homogeneous pieces?
You are right! I will now correct this.
Thank you for the detailed proof. This is essentially the argument I was already using in my book when I asked the question. I guess the consensus is that it is the most direct proof that OCA CH, although I still wonder if anyone has seriously tried to directly construct a counterexample to OCA using CH.
Incidentally, your proof of “Alternative 2” is not correct — you only have . I noticed the same error in Velickovic’s paper. I don’t have access to Todorcevic’s book at the moment, I wonder if the error tracks back to it?
Thanks, Nik. I’m afraid I don’t have a copy of neither, but you are of course right concerning Alternative 2.
Nevertheless, this is easy to fix: by item (3), we may find some such that . Pick such that . Then cannot be an integer.
The post has just been corrected.
Nice! I had a slightly different way of fixing the problem, but yours is faster. (Extend each to a piecewise linear function from to , then look at the graphs of these functions in . The gap between the graph of each function and its successor is open, and you can’t have uncountably many disjoint open subsets of .)
btw, there is a somewhat different proof: use properties (1)–(3) of the -scale to construct a subfamily of such that admits no uncoutnable chains or antichains. Then, prove that SOCA entails that any uncountable subposet of either contains an uncounatble chain, or an uncountable antichain.
I think that the discussion went deeper than it should if one is interested only in why OGA (TA) implies non-CH. However, it should be pointed out that the proof is of twofold independent interest. (see Todorcevic’s ‘Partition Problem in Topology’ , Theorems 3.4 and 8.5 , or the proof of Theorem 8.6). Second, it shows that there exist two sets of reals of cardinality which are orthogonal to each other in the sense that they contain no isomorphic copy of the same linear ordering of cardinality . Thus, also contradicts Baumgartner’s axiom.
relevance of the
First, it forms a part of the much deeper fact that OGA (TA) implies that
If you are interested in mathematically and historically more basic reasons of why OGA (TA) implies non-CH simply remember that there is a mapping from the reals into the reals which is not continuous on any set of reals of cardinality continuum or remember that under CH were is a Luzin subset of the Cantor set and consider the natural open graphs associated to these objects.