Recall that a coloring of an (undirected) graph is said to be chromatic if whenever . Then, the chromatic number of a graph is the least cardinal for which there exists a chromatic coloring .
Motivated by a paper I found yesterday in the arXiv, this post will be dedicated to exemplifying incompactness properties of the chromatic number measure. More specifically, we shall give a construction of Shelah, of a graph of size such that all of its subgraphs of size are countably chromatic, while the graph itself is not.
Before stating and proving Shelah’s theorem, we mention a somewhat simpler (yet, canonical) test-case. To every cardinal , one associates the Erdos-Hajnal graph , where stands for the set being bounded in . Here is a list of fairly simple observations:
- if is a regular cardinal, then any subgraph of of size is countably chromatic;
- the chromatic number of equals ;
- the chromatic number of is bigger than ;
- if is a graph of size such that every subgraph of size is countably chromatic, then the chromatic number of is the chromatic number of . This shows that is a canonical witness to incompactness of this sort, whenever exists.
- why did I write “whenever exists” in the previous item? well, for instance, if is a measurable cardinal, then every function is fixed on a measure one set, and hence is countably chromatic!
Update (November, 2015): See the interesting discussion in the comments below.
Now, on to the theorem.
Theorem (Shelah, 2012). Suppose that is a regular cardinal .
If admits a non-reflecting stationary subset, and for all , then there exists a graph of size such that any of its subgraphs of size is countably chromatic, while is not countably chromatic.
In particular, the above assumptions entails that is not countably chromatic.
Proof. Fix a regressive surjection such that the preimage of every singleton is cofinal in . Denote . Let be a non-reflecting stationary subset, and put .
As the underlying set of our graph, we take:
Next, we fix a club guessing sequence . For all , let denote the increasing enumeration of . Let denote the collection of all sequences that satisfies for all :
As , we may fix a surjection .
Finally, the set of edges of the constructed graph will be:
Subclaim. is not countably chromatic.
Proof. Suppose not, as witnessed by some coloring . For each , let . Then is a descending chain, and since , the chain must stabilize at some . Denote .
Consider the club
Pick such that .
It follows that we may find a sequence such that for all :
Pick such that . Then for all , we have , and hence . In particular,
On the other hand, , and so . This is a contradiction.
Write , where .
Note. if , then .
Proof. If , then and . As , while , we infer that , and so .
Note also that if , then .
Main subclaim. Suppose that is an infinite subset of .
Then, for every with , and a chromatic coloring , there exists a chromatic coloring such that , and .
Proof. Given , let be some partition of into mutually-disjoint infinite sets. We now prove the claim by induction on .
The case is trivial.
If is a limit non-zero ordinal, let us pick a club in such that . As is non-reflecting, we may moreover assume that .
Now, build an ascending chain of chromatic colorings by induction on :
- for , let ;
- for , let , and . Then , and , so by the induction hypothesis, we may pick a chromatic coloring that extends , and such that .
- for , let . Then is chromatic as the limit of chromatic colorings.
Finally, put . Then has all the desired properties.
If is a successor ordinal, and , then , and so we may appeal to the induction hypothesis for .
If is a successor ordinal, and , let us denote . Since and , we get that , so let us fix a large enough so that .
Let
- for all ;
- , and for all .
Note that for all , we have and .
So it follows from the induction hypothesis, that there exists an increasing chain of chromatic colorings that extends , and such that , for all . Note that .
Finally, let be some coloring that satisfies:
We need to verify that is chromatic.
For this, fix such that , and let us verify that .
Of course, we may assume that , because otherwise for some .
Next, by the definition of , there exists , , and such that:
As , we know that . In addition, , because otherwise , contradicting the fact that .
So , that is , and since , we conclude that , and .
Now, if , then by the very choice of , we have
If , then is a natural number, and so entails
Since , we get that . Since is regressive, we get that . Altogether, and hence
In particular, This concludes the last case.
This completes the proof of the main submclaim.
It follows from the main subclaim that for every , the subgraph is countably chromatic. As is regular, this in particular entails that every subgraph of of size is countably chromatic.
Corollary. If is a strong limit singular cardinal, and is countably chromatic, then exists.
Proof. The covering lemma implies and for every strong limit singular cardinal . implies that every stationary subset of admits a non-reflecting stationary subset.
The preceding is of no surprise, as previously Todorcevic proved that if is an infinite cardinal and is countably chromatic, then .
We conclude this post by providing proofs to several easy facts (some of which were mentioned in the introduction).
Fact. if is a regular cardinal, then any subgraph of of size is countably chromatic.
Proof. Suppose that is a regular cardinal, and is a family of less than many functions from to . For such that , denote Let . As , we get that . Define by letting for all . Now, if and , then for all and hence is a chromatic coloring.
Fact. If is a graph of size such that every subgraph of size is countably chromatic, then the chromatic number of is the chromatic number of .
Proof. Without loss of generality, . For every , let exemplify that is countably chromatic.
Next, for all , define by letting for all :Note that if , then (indeed, ). So, is a graph homomorphism, and the chromatic number of is the one of .
Corollary. The chromatic number of is at least .
Fact. The chromatic number of equals .
Proof. Clearly, the chromatic number of is . Next, fix an injection . For every , let be the function defined by , for all . Notice that if are distinct infinite subsets of , then . It follows that any chromatic coloring of must be injective over , and hence the chromatic number of equals .
Fact. Suppose that is an -tree. Let denote the comparability graph of . If is countably chromatic, then is a special Aronszajn tree.
Proof. Recall that , where . Now, if is a chain, then any chromatic coloring of must be injective over . In particular, if is countably chromatic, then is Aronszajn. Moreover, if is a chromatic coloring, then it is easy to construct an order-preserving function . Simply define for all by induction on , while insuring that is finite for all .
Trivia. Todorcevic proved that after Levy collapsing a supercompact to , the following statement holds in the extension. If is a tree for which is not countably chromatic, then some subtree already has the property that is not countably chromatic.
Pingback: Assaf Rinot: On incompactness for chromatic number of graphs | Set Theory Talks
A PDF file with lecture notes for today’s talk on this subject, is available here.
Great talk. I really enjoyed it. , instead of using for . -sequence.
1. In the last case of the main subclaim, I feel it might be simpler just staying with
2. I am not familiar with club guessing sequence. I’d like to ask you next week about how to get the
Thanks a lot, Shi! is to allow to fluently speak about .
2. Here is a proof of this form of club-guessing. Suppose , and is stationary. For every , pick a cofinal subset of order-type . Given a club , denote Notice that as is a club, we get that . Notice also that if , then is a cofinal subset of of order-type .
1. The choice of
We claim that there exists a club for which guesses clubs. That is, for every club , there exists some such that .
Suppose not. Then there exists a decreasing and continuous chain of clubs such that , and for all .
As is a decreasing chain, for all , the sequence of ordinals is weakly decreasing, and hence must stabilize at some .
Put . Then is a club, so let us fix some .
Let . Then , and for all . It follows that and , contradicting the choice of .
Thanks. This is helpful. I can see how to get the -sequence now.
I very much liked this post. The two last facts have slightly easier proofs, it seems: : we don’t need , just let be the n-th element in the increasing enumeration of . For the special Aronszajn trees: if we use the original definition that an tree is special if it is a union of countably many antichains then the fact is really obvious.
the chromatic number of
Thanks a LOT Mirna! This is a fun subject! ’s. If I’d naively take and , then the corresponding enumerating functions will not be -adjacent.
You are of course right – the claim about special Aronszajn trees is obvious. It is just that I was always under the impression that the definition of “speciality” of trees stemmed as an order-oriented concept, rather than a graph-theoretic one.
About the countable X’s – this surely works for a clever choice of a family of
You seem to be unaware of the fact that thirty years earlier in Theorem 8 of
Todorčević, S. On a conjecture of R. Rado. J. London Math. Soc. (2) 27 (1983), no. 1, 1–8
a stronger result is proved. You seem also unaware of the fact that the chromatic number of is bigger than .
Are these results comparable? Todorcevic’s conclusion is stronger in the sense that the incompact graph is moreover a tree. On the other hand, it appears that the incompactness there is restricted only to subgraphs of size , whereas here incompactness is witnessed on any small subgraph.
The fact about is mentioned as the third bullet in the above introduction.
Yes the results are comparable! Did you read the proof? Did you notice Claims 1 and 2? Did you notice that Claim 2 asserts that all subtrees of size $
I just read the proof, and agree that Theorem 8 is stronger. entails a nonspecial tree of size all of which smaller subtrees are special.
So, the existence of a nonreflecting stationary subset of
The claim of Stevo must be mistaken (although I can’t find this assertion in the linked paper). If there is an aleph_1 dense ideal on aleph_1 and CH holds, then there is a uniform ultrafilter on aleph_1 such that the ultrapower of aleph_0 has only aleph_1 many equivalence classes. This induces a graph coloring of EH(aleph_1) in aleph_1 colors. This is the same argument as Foreman gives for what his model satisfies about EH(aleph_2).
Thanks, Monroe! This is stated right after Question 8.3 in here. Indeed, the linked paper provides another result, namely, that is uncountably chromatic. The post has been corrected accordingly.